ART

In physics, hidden-variable theories are proposals to provide deterministic explanations of quantum mechanical phenomena, through the introduction of unobservable hypothetical entities. The existence of indeterminacy for some measurements is assumed as part of the mathematical formulation of quantum mechanics; moreover, bounds for indeterminacy can be expressed in a quantitative form by the Heisenberg uncertainty principle.

Albert Einstein objected to the fundamentally probabilistic nature of quantum mechanics,[1] and famously declared "I am convinced God does not play dice".[2][3] Einstein, Podolsky, and Rosen argued that quantum mechanics is an incomplete description of reality.[4][5] Bell's theorem would later suggest that local hidden variables (a way for finding a complete description of reality) of certain types are impossible. A famous non-local theory is the De Broglie–Bohm theory.

Motivation

Per its mathematical formulation, quantum mechanics is non-deterministic, meaning that it generally does not predict the outcome of any measurement with certainty. Instead, it indicates what the probabilities of the outcomes are, with the indeterminism of observable quantities constrained by the uncertainty principle. The question arises whether there might be some deeper reality hidden beneath quantum mechanics, to be described by a more fundamental theory that can always predict the outcome of each measurement with certainty: if the exact properties of every subatomic particle were known the entire system could be modeled exactly using deterministic physics similar to classical physics.

In other words, it is conceivable that quantum mechanics is an incomplete description of nature. The designation of variables as underlying "hidden" variables depends on the level of physical description (so, for example, "if a gas is described in terms of temperature, pressure, and volume, then the velocities of the individual atoms in the gas would be hidden variables"[6]). Physicists supporting De Broglie–Bohm theory maintain that underlying the observed probabilistic nature of the universe is a deterministic objective foundation/property—the hidden variable. Others, however, believe that there is no deeper deterministic reality in quantum mechanics.

A lack of a kind of realism (understood here as asserting independent existence and evolution of physical quantities, such as position or momentum, without the process of measurement) is crucial in the Copenhagen interpretation. Realistic interpretations (which were already incorporated, to an extent, into the physics of Feynman[7]), on the other hand, assume that particles have certain trajectories. Under such view, these trajectories will almost always be continuous, which follows both from the finitude of the perceived speed of light ("leaps" should rather be precluded) and, more importantly, from the principle of least action, as deduced in quantum physics by Dirac. But continuous movement, in accordance with the mathematical definition, implies deterministic movement for a range of time arguments;[8] and thus realism is, under modern physics, one more reason for seeking (at least certain limited) determinism and thus a hidden-variable theory (especially that such theory exists: see De Broglie–Bohm interpretation).

Although determinism was initially a major motivation for physicists looking for hidden-variable theories, non-deterministic theories trying to explain what the supposed reality underlying the quantum mechanics formalism looks like are also considered hidden-variable theories; for example Edward Nelson's stochastic mechanics.
"God does not play dice"

In June 1926, Max Born published a paper, "Zur Quantenmechanik der Stoßvorgänge" ("Quantum Mechanics of Collision Phenomena") in the scientific journal Zeitschrift für Physik, in which he was the first to clearly enunciate the probabilistic interpretation of the quantum wave function, which had been introduced by Erwin Schrödinger earlier in the year. Born concluded the paper as follows:

Here the whole problem of determinism comes up. From the standpoint of our quantum mechanics there is no quantity which in any individual case causally fixes the consequence of the collision; but also experimentally we have so far no reason to believe that there are some inner properties of the atom which conditions a definite outcome for the collision. Ought we to hope later to discover such properties ... and determine them in individual cases? Or ought we to believe that the agreement of theory and experiment—as to the impossibility of prescribing conditions for a causal evolution—is a pre-established harmony founded on the nonexistence of such conditions? I myself am inclined to give up determinism in the world of atoms. But that is a philosophical question for which physical arguments alone are not decisive.

Born's interpretation of the wave function was criticized by Schrödinger, who had previously attempted to interpret it in real physical terms, but Albert Einstein's response became one of the earliest and most famous assertions that quantum mechanics is incomplete:

Quantum mechanics is very worthy of respect. But an inner voice tells me this is not the genuine article after all. The theory delivers much but it hardly brings us closer to the Old One's secret. In any event, I am convinced that He is not playing dice.[3][9]

Niels Bohr reportedly replied to Einstein's later expression of this sentiment by advising him to "stop telling God what to do."[10]
Early attempts at hidden-variable theories

Shortly after making his famous "God does not play dice" comment, Einstein attempted to formulate a deterministic counter proposal to quantum mechanics, presenting a paper at a meeting of the Academy of Sciences in Berlin, on 5 May 1927, titled "Bestimmt Schrödinger's Wellenmechanik die Bewegung eines Systems vollständig oder nur im Sinne der Statistik?" ("Does Schrödinger's wave mechanics determine the motion of a system completely or only in the statistical sense?").[11][12] However, as the paper was being prepared for publication in the academy's journal, Einstein decided to withdraw it, possibly because he discovered that, contrary to his intention, it implied non-separability of entangled systems, which he regarded as absurd.[13]

At the Fifth Solvay Congress, held in Belgium in October 1927 and attended by all the major theoretical physicists of the era, Louis de Broglie presented his own version of a deterministic hidden-variable theory, apparently unaware of Einstein's aborted attempt earlier in the year. In his theory, every particle had an associated, hidden "pilot wave" which served to guide its trajectory through space. The theory was subject to criticism at the Congress, particularly by Wolfgang Pauli, which de Broglie did not adequately answer. De Broglie abandoned the theory shortly thereafter.
Declaration of completeness of quantum mechanics, and the Bohr–Einstein debates
Main article: Bohr–Einstein debates

Also at the Fifth Solvay Congress, Max Born and Werner Heisenberg made a presentation summarizing the recent tremendous theoretical development of quantum mechanics. At the conclusion of the presentation, they declared:

[W]hile we consider ... a quantum mechanical treatment of the electromagnetic field ... as not yet finished, we consider quantum mechanics to be a closed theory, whose fundamental physical and mathematical assumptions are no longer susceptible of any modification.... On the question of the 'validity of the law of causality' we have this opinion: as long as one takes into account only experiments that lie in the domain of our currently acquired physical and quantum mechanical experience, the assumption of indeterminism in principle, here taken as fundamental, agrees with experience.[14]

Although there is no record of Einstein responding to Born and Heisenberg during the technical sessions of the Fifth Solvay Congress, he did challenge the completeness of quantum mechanics during informal discussions over meals, presenting a thought experiment intended to demonstrate that quantum mechanics could not be entirely correct. He did likewise during the Sixth Solvay Congress held in 1930. Both times, Niels Bohr is generally considered to have successfully defended quantum mechanics by discovering errors in Einstein's arguments.
EPR paradox
Main article: EPR paradox

The debates between Bohr and Einstein essentially concluded in 1935, when Einstein finally expressed what is widely considered his best argument against the completeness of quantum mechanics. Einstein, Podolsky, and Rosen had proposed their definition of a "complete" description as one that uniquely determines the values of all its measurable properties.[15] Einstein later summarized their argument as follows:

Consider a mechanical system consisting of two partial systems A and B which interact with each other only during a limited time. Let the ψ function [i.e., wavefunction] before their interaction be given. Then the Schrödinger equation will furnish the ψ function after the interaction has taken place. Let us now determine the physical state of the partial system A as completely as possible by measurements. Then quantum mechanics allows us to determine the ψ function of the partial system B from the measurements made, and from the ψ function of the total system. This determination, however, gives a result which depends upon which of the physical quantities (observables) of A have been measured (for instance, coordinates or momenta). Since there can be only one physical state of B after the interaction which cannot reasonably be considered to depend on the particular measurement we perform on the system A separated from B it may be concluded that the ψ function is not unambiguously coordinated to the physical state. This coordination of several ψ functions to the same physical state of system B shows again that the ψ function cannot be interpreted as a (complete) description of a physical state of a single system.[16]

Bohr answered Einstein's challenge as follows:

[The argument of] Einstein, Podolsky and Rosen contains an ambiguity as regards the meaning of the expression "without in any way disturbing a system." ... [E]ven at this stage [i.e., the measurement of, for example, a particle that is part of an entangled pair], there is essentially the question of an influence on the very conditions which define the possible types of predictions regarding the future behavior of the system. Since these conditions constitute an inherent element of the description of any phenomenon to which the term "physical reality" can be properly attached, we see that the argumentation of the mentioned authors does not justify their conclusion that quantum-mechanical description is essentially incomplete."[17]

Bohr is here choosing to define a "physical reality" as limited to a phenomenon that is immediately observable by an arbitrarily chosen and explicitly specified technique, using his own special definition of the term 'phenomenon'. He wrote in 1948:

As a more appropriate way of expression, one may strongly advocate limitation of the use of the word phenomenon to refer exclusively to observations obtained under specified circumstances, including an account of the whole experiment."[18][19]

This was, of course, in conflict with the definition used by the EPR paper, as follows:

If, without in any way disturbing a system, we can predict with certainty (i.e., with probability equal to unity) the value of a physical quantity, then there exists an element of physical reality corresponding to this physical quantity. [Italics in original][4]

Bell's theorem
Main article: Bell's theorem

In 1964, John Bell showed through his famous theorem that if local hidden variables exist, certain experiments could be performed involving quantum entanglement where the result would satisfy a Bell inequality. If, on the other hand, statistical correlations resulting from quantum entanglement could not be explained by local hidden variables, the Bell inequality would be violated. Another no-go theorem concerning hidden-variable theories is the Kochen–Specker theorem.

Physicists such as Alain Aspect and Paul Kwiat have performed experiments that have found violations of these inequalities up to 242 standard deviations[20] (excellent scientific certainty). This rules out local hidden-variable theories, but does not rule out non-local ones. Theoretically, there could be experimental problems that affect the validity of the experimental findings.

Gerard 't Hooft has disputed the validity of Bell's theorem on the basis of the superdeterminism loophole and proposed some ideas to construct local deterministic models.[21]
Bohm's hidden-variable theory
Main article: de Broglie–Bohm theory

Assuming the validity of Bell's theorem, any deterministic hidden-variable theory that is consistent with quantum mechanics would have to be non-local, maintaining the existence of instantaneous or faster-than-light relations (correlations) between physically separated entities. The currently best-known hidden-variable theory, the "causal" interpretation of the physicist and philosopher David Bohm, originally published in 1952, is a non-local hidden-variable theory. Bohm unknowingly rediscovered (and extended) the idea that Louis de Broglie had proposed in 1927 (and abandoned) – hence this theory is commonly called "de Broglie-Bohm theory". Bohm posited both the quantum particle, e.g. an electron, and a hidden 'guiding wave' that governs its motion. Thus, in this theory electrons are quite clearly particles—when a double-slit experiment is performed, its trajectory goes through one slit rather than the other. Also, the slit passed through is not random but is governed by the (hidden) guiding wave, resulting in the wave pattern that is observed. Since the location where the particles start in the double-slit experiment is unknown, the initial position of the particle is the hidden variable.

Such a view does not contradict the idea of local events that is used in both classical atomism and relativity theory as Bohm's theory (and quantum mechanics) are still locally causal (that is, information travel is still restricted to the speed of light) but allow non-local correlations. It points to a view of a more holistic, mutually interpenetrating and interacting world. Indeed, Bohm himself stressed the holistic aspect of quantum theory in his later years, when he became interested in the ideas of Jiddu Krishnamurti.

In Bohm's interpretation, the (non-local) quantum potential constitutes an implicate (hidden) order which organizes a particle, and which may itself be the result of yet a further implicate order: a superimplicate order which organizes a field.[22] Nowadays Bohm's theory is considered to be one of many interpretations of quantum mechanics which give a realist interpretation, and not merely a positivistic one, to quantum-mechanical calculations. Some consider it the simplest theory to explain quantum phenomena.[23] Nevertheless, it is a hidden-variable theory, and necessarily so.[24] The major reference for Bohm's theory today is his book with Basil Hiley, published posthumously.[25]

A possible weakness of Bohm's theory is that some (including Einstein, Pauli, and Heisenberg) feel that it looks contrived.[26] (Indeed, Bohm thought this of his original formulation of the theory.[27]) It was deliberately designed to give predictions that are in all details identical to conventional quantum mechanics.[27] Bohm's original aim was not to make a serious counter proposal but simply to demonstrate that hidden-variable theories are indeed possible.[27] (It thus provided a supposed counterexample to the famous proof by John von Neumann that was generally believed to demonstrate that no deterministic theory reproducing the statistical predictions of quantum mechanics is possible.) Bohm said he considered his theory to be unacceptable as a physical theory due to the guiding wave's existence in an abstract multi-dimensional configuration space, rather than three-dimensional space.[27] His hope was that the theory would lead to new insights and experiments that would lead ultimately to an acceptable one;[27] his aim was not to set out a deterministic, mechanical viewpoint, but rather to show that it was possible to attribute properties to an underlying reality, in contrast to the conventional approach to quantum mechanics.[28]
Recent developments

In August 2011, Roger Colbeck and Renato Renner published a proof that any extension of quantum mechanical theory, whether using hidden variables or otherwise, cannot provide a more accurate prediction of outcomes, assuming that observers can freely choose the measurement settings.[29] Colbeck and Renner write: "In the present work, we have ... excluded the possibility that any extension of quantum theory (not necessarily in the form of local hidden variables) can help predict the outcomes of any measurement on any quantum state. In this sense, we show the following: under the assumption that measurement settings can be chosen freely, quantum theory really is complete".

In January 2013, Giancarlo Ghirardi and Raffaele Romano described a model which, "under a different free choice assumption [...] violates [the statement by Colbeck and Renner] for almost all states of a bipartite two-level system, in a possibly experimentally testable way".[30]
See also

Local hidden-variable theory
Bell's theorem
Bell test experiments
Einstein's thought experiments
Quantum mechanics
Bohm interpretation
Spekkens toy model

References

The Born-Einstein letters: correspondence between Albert Einstein and Max and Hedwig Born from 1916–1955, with commentaries by Max Born. Macmillan. 1971. p. 158., (Private letter from Einstein to Max Born, 3 March 1947: "I admit, of course, that there is a considerable amount of validity in the statistical approach which you were the first to recognize clearly as necessary given the framework of the existing formalism. I cannot seriously believe in it because the theory cannot be reconciled with the idea that physics should represent a reality in time and space, free from spooky actions at a distance.... I am quite convinced that someone will eventually come up with a theory whose objects, connected by laws, are not probabilities but considered facts, as used to be taken for granted until quite recently".)
This is a common paraphrase of a sentence in a private letter from Einstein to Max Born, 4 December 1926, Albert Einstein Archives reel 8, item 180
The Collected Papers of Albert Einstein, Volume 15: The Berlin Years: Writings & Correspondence, June 1925-May 1927 (English Translation Supplement), p. 403
Einstein, A.; Podolsky, B.; Rosen, N. (1935). "Can Quantum-Mechanical Description of Physical Reality Be Considered Complete?". Physical Review. 47 (10): 777–780. Bibcode:1935PhRv...47..777E. doi:10.1103/PhysRev.47.777.
"The debate whether Quantum Mechanics is a complete theory and probabilities have a non-epistemic character (i.e. nature is intrinsically probabilistic) or whether it is a statistical approximation of a deterministic theory and probabilities are due to our ignorance of some parameters (i.e. they are epistemic) dates to the beginning of the theory itself". See:arXiv:quant-ph/0701071v1 12 Jan 2007
Senechal M, Cronin J (2001). "Social influences on quantum mechanics?-I". The Mathematical Intelligencer. 23 (4): 15–17. doi:10.1007/BF03024596.
Individual diagrams are often split into several parts, which may occur beyond observation; only the diagram as a whole describes an observed event.
For every subset of points within a range, a value for every argument from the subset will be determined by the points in the neighbourhood. Thus, as a whole, the evolution in time can be described (for a specific time interval) as a function, e.g. a linear one or an arc. See Continuous function#Definition in terms of limits of functions
The Born–Einstein letters: correspondence between Albert Einstein and Max and Hedwig Born from 1916–1955, with commentaries by Max Born. Macmillan. 1971. p. 91.
This is a common paraphrasing. Bohr recollected his reply to Einstein at the 1927 Solvay Congress in his essay "Discussion with Einstein on Epistemological Problems in Atomic Physics", in Albert Einstein, Philosopher–Scientist, ed. Paul Arthur Shilpp, Harper, 1949, p. 211: "...in spite of all divergencies of approach and opinion, a most humorous spirit animated the discussions. On his side, Einstein mockingly asked us whether we could really believe that the providential authorities took recourse to dice-playing ("ob der liebe Gott würfelt"), to which I replied by pointing at the great caution, already called for by ancient thinkers, in ascribing attributes to Providence in everyday language." Werner Heisenberg, who also attended the congress, recalled the exchange in Encounters with Einstein, Princeton University Press, 1983, p. 117,: "But he [Einstein] still stood by his watchword, which he clothed in the words: 'God does not play at dice.' To which Bohr could only answer: 'But still, it cannot be for us to tell God, how he is to run the world.'"
The Collected Papers of Albert Einstein, Volume 15: The Berlin Years: Writings & Correspondence, June 1925-May 1927 (English Translation Supplement), p. 512
Albert Einstein Archives reel 2, item 100
Baggott, Jim (2011). The Quantum Story: A History in 40 Moments. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 116–117.
Max Born and Werner Heisenberg, "Quantum mechanics", proceedings of the Fifth Solvay Congress.
Einstein, A.; Podolsky, B.; Rosen, N. (1935). "Can Quantum-Mechanical Description of Physical Reality Be Considered Complete?". Physical Review. 47 (10): 777–780. Bibcode:1935PhRv...47..777E. doi:10.1103/physrev.47.777.
Einstein A (1936). "Physics and Reality". Journal of the Franklin Institute. 221.
Bohr N (1935). "Can Quantum-Mechanical Description of Physical Reality be Considered Complete?". Physical Review. 48 (8): 700. Bibcode:1935PhRv...48..696B. doi:10.1103/physrev.48.696.
Bohr N. (1948). "On the notions of causality and complementarity". Dialectica. 2 (3–4): 312–319 [317]. doi:10.1111/j.1746-8361.1948.tb00703.x.
Rosenfeld, L. (). 'Niels Bohr's contribution to epistemology', pp. 522–535 in Selected Papers of Léon Rosenfeld, Cohen, R.S., Stachel, J.J. (editors), D. Riedel, Dordrecht, ISBN 978-90-277-0652-2, p. 531: "Moreover, the complete definition of the phenomenon must essentially contain the indication of some permanent mark left upon a recording device which is part of the apparatus; only by thus envisaging the phenomenon as a closed event, terminated by a permanent record, can we do justice to the typical wholeness of the quantal processes."
Kwiat P. G.; et al. (1999). "Ultrabright source of polarization-entangled photons". Physical Review A. 60 (2): R773–R776.arXiv:quant-ph/9810003. Bibcode:1999PhRvA..60..773K. doi:10.1103/physreva.60.r773.
G 't Hooft, The Free-Will Postulate in Quantum Mechanics [1]; Entangled quantum states in a local deterministic theory [2]
David Pratt: "David Bohm and the Implicate Order". Appeared in Sunrise magazine, February/March 1993, Theosophical University Press
Michael K.-H. Kiessling: "Misleading Signposts Along the de Broglie–Bohm Road to Quantum Mechanics", Foundations of Physics, volume 40, number 4, 2010, pp. 418–429 (abstract)
"While the testable predictions of Bohmian mechanics are isomorphic to standard Copenhagen quantum mechanics, its underlying hidden variables have to be, in principle, unobservable. If one could observe them, one would be able to take advantage of that and signal faster than light, which – according to the special theory of relativity – leads to physical temporal paradoxes." J. Kofler and A. Zeiliinger, "Quantum Information and Randomness", European Review (2010), Vol. 18, No. 4, 469–480.
D. Bohm and B. J. Hiley, The Undivided Universe, Routledge, 1993, ISBN 0-415-06588-7.
Wayne C. Myrvold (2003). "On some early objections to Bohm's theory" (PDF). International Studies in the Philosophy of Science. 17 (1): 8–24. doi:10.1080/02698590305233. Archived from the original on 2014-07-02.
David Bohm (1957). Causality and Chance in Modern Physics. Routledge & Kegan Paul and D. Van Nostrand. p. 110. ISBN 0-8122-1002-6.
B. J. Hiley: Some remarks on the evolution of Bohm's proposals for an alternative to quantum mechanics, 30 January 2010
Roger Colbeck; Renato Renner (2011). "No extension of quantum theory can have improved predictive power". Nature Communications. 2 (8): 411.arXiv:1005.5173. Bibcode:2011NatCo...2E.411C. doi:10.1038/ncomms1416. PMID 21811240.

Giancarlo Ghirardi; Raffaele Romano (2013). "Onthological models predictively inequivalent to quantum theory". Physical Review Letters. 110 (17): 170404.arXiv:1301.2695. Bibcode:2013PhRvL.110q0404G. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.110.170404. PMID 23679689.

Bibliography

This further reading section may contain inappropriate or excessive suggestions that may not follow Wikipedia's guidelines. Please ensure that only a reasonable number of balanced, topical, reliable, and notable further reading suggestions are given; removing less relevant or redundant publications with the same point of view where appropriate. Consider utilising appropriate texts as inline sources or creating a separate bibliography article. (June 2019) (Learn how and when to remove this template message)

Einstein, Albert; Podolsky, Boris; Rosen, Nathan (1935). "Can Quantum-Mechanical Description of Physical Reality Be Considered Complete?". Physical Review. 47 (10): 777–780. Bibcode:1935PhRv...47..777E. doi:10.1103/physrev.47.777.
Bell, John Stewart (1964). "On the Einstein–Podolsky–Rosen paradox". Physics Physique Физика. 1 (3): 195–200. doi:10.1103/physicsphysiquefizika.1.195. Reprinted in Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Mechanics. Cambridge University Press. 2004.
Bohm, D.; Hiley, B. J. (1993). The Undivided Universe. Routledge.
Pauli, Wolfgang (1988). "Letter to M. Fierz dated 10 August 1954". Beyond the Atom: The Philosophical Thought of Wolfgang Pauli. Translated by Laurikainen, K. V. Berlin: Springer-Verlag. p. 226.
Heisenberg, Werner (1971). Physics and Beyond: Encounters and Conversations. Translated by Pomerans, A. J. New York: Harper & Row. pp. 63–64.
Cohen-Tannoudji, Claude; Diu, Bernard; Laloë, Franck (1982). Quantum Mechanics. Translated by Hemley, Susan; Ostrowsky, Nicole; Ostrowsky, Dan. John Wiley & Sons.
Hanle, P. S. (1979). "Indeterminacy before Heisenberg: The Case of Franz Exner and Erwin Schrödinger". Historical Studies in the Physical Sciences. 10: 225–269. doi:10.2307/27757391. JSTOR 27757391.
Peres, Asher; Zurek, Wojciech (1982). "Is quantum theory universally valid?". American Journal of Physics. 50 (9): 807–810. doi:10.1119/1.13086.
Zurek, Wojciech (1982). "Environment-induced superselection rules". Physical Review. D. 26 (8): 1862–1880. Bibcode:1982PhRvD..26.1862Z. doi:10.1103/physrevd.26.1862.
Jammer, Max (1985). "The EPR Problem in Its Historical Development". In Lahti, P.; Mittelstaedt, P. (eds.). Symposium on the Foundations of Modern Physics: 50 years of the Einstein–Podolsky–Rosen Gedankenexperiment. Singapore: World Scientific. pp. 129–149.
Fine, Arthur (1986). The Shaky Game: Einstein Realism and the Quantum Theory. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Kuhn, Thomas (1987). Black-Body Theory and the Quantum Discontinuity, 1894-1912. Chicago University Press.
Peres, Asher (1993). Quantum Theory: Concepts and Methods. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Caves, Carlton M.; Fuchs, Christopher A. (1996). "Quantum Information: How Much Information in a State Vector?". In Mann, A.; Revzen, M. (eds.). The Dilemma of Einstein, Podolsky and Rosen – 60 Years Later. Ann. Israel Physical Society. 12. pp. 226–257.
Rovelli, Carlo (1996). "Relational quantum mechanics". International Journal of Theoretical Physics. 35 (8): 1637–1678.arXiv:quant-ph/9609002. Bibcode:1996IJTP...35.1637R. doi:10.1007/bf02302261.
Omnès, Roland (1999). Understanding Quantum Mechanics. Princeton University Press.
Jackiw, Roman; Kleppner, Daniel (2000). "One Hundred Years of Quantum Physics". Science. 289 (5481): 893–8.arXiv:quant-ph/0008092. doi:10.1126/science.289.5481.893. PMID 17839156.
Alter, Orly; Yamamoto, Yoshihisa (2001). Quantum Measurement of a Single System. Wiley-Interscience. doi:10.1002/9783527617128. ISBN 9780471283089.
Joos, Erich; et al. (2003). Decoherence and the Appearance of a Classical World in Quantum Theory (2nd ed.). Berlin: Springer.
Zurek, Wojciech (2003). "Decoherence and the transition from quantum to classical — Revisited".arXiv:quant-ph/0306072. (An updated version of Physics Today, 44:36–44 (1991) article)
Zurek, Wojciech. "Decoherence, einselection, and the quantum origins of the classical". Reviews of Modern Physics. 75: 715.arXiv:quant-ph/0105127. doi:10.1103/RevModPhys.75.715.
Peres, Asher; Terno, Daniel (2004). "Quantum Information and Relativity Theory". Reviews of Modern Physics. 76 (1): 93–123.arXiv:quant-ph/0212023. Bibcode:2004RvMP...76...93P. doi:10.1103/revmodphys.76.93.
Penrose, Roger (2004). The Road to Reality: A Complete Guide to the Laws of the Universe. Alfred Knopf.
Schlosshauer, Maximilian (2005). "Decoherence, the Measurement Problem, and Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics". Reviews of Modern Physics. 76 (4): 1267–1305.arXiv:quant-ph/0312059. Bibcode:2004RvMP...76.1267S. doi:10.1103/revmodphys.76.1267.
Laudisa, Federico; Rovelli, Carlo. "Relational Quantum Mechanics". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2005 ed.).
Genovese, Marco (2005). "Research on hidden variable theories: a review of recent progresses". Physics Reports. 413 (6): 319–396.arXiv:quant-ph/0701071. doi:10.1016/j.physrep.2005.03.003.

vte

Quantum mechanics
Background

Introduction History
timeline Glossary Classical mechanics Old quantum theory

Fundamentals

Bra–ket notation Casimir effect Coherence Coherent control Complementarity Density matrix Energy level
degenerate levels excited state ground state QED vacuum QCD vacuum Vacuum state Zero-point energy Hamiltonian Heisenberg uncertainty principle Pauli exclusion principle Measurement Observable Operator Probability distribution Quantum Qubit Qutrit Scattering theory Spin Spontaneous parametric down-conversion Symmetry Symmetry breaking
Spontaneous symmetry breaking No-go theorem No-cloning theorem Von Neumann entropy Wave interference Wave function
collapse Universal wavefunction Wave–particle duality
Matter wave Wave propagation Virtual particle

Quantum

quantum coherence annealing decoherence entanglement fluctuation foam levitation noise nonlocality number realm state superposition system tunnelling Quantum vacuum state

Mathematics
Equations

Dirac Klein–Gordon Pauli Rydberg Schrödinger

Formulations

Heisenberg Interaction Matrix mechanics Path integral formulation Phase space Schrödinger

Other

Quantum
algebra calculus
differential stochastic geometry group Q-analog
List

Interpretations

Bayesian Consistent histories Cosmological Copenhagen de Broglie–Bohm Ensemble Hidden variables Many worlds Objective collapse Quantum logic Relational Stochastic Transactional

Experiments

Afshar Bell's inequality Cold Atom Laboratory Davisson–Germer Delayed-choice quantum eraser Double-slit Elitzur–Vaidman Franck–Hertz experiment Leggett–Garg inequality Mach-Zehnder inter. Popper Quantum eraser Quantum suicide and immortality Schrödinger's cat Stern–Gerlach Wheeler's delayed choice

Science

Measurement problem QBism

Quantum

biology chemistry chaos cognition complexity theory computing
Timeline cosmology dynamics economics finance foundations game theory information nanoscience metrology mind optics probability social science spacetime

Technologies

Quantum technology
links Matrix isolation Phase qubit Quantum dot
cellular automaton display laser single-photon source solar cell Quantum well
laser

Extensions

Dirac sea Fractional quantum mechanics Quantum electrodynamics
links Quantum geometry Quantum field theory
links Quantum gravity
links Quantum information science
links Quantum statistical mechanics Relativistic quantum mechanics De Broglie–Bohm theory Stochastic electrodynamics

Related

Quantum mechanics of time travel Textbooks

Physics Encyclopedia

World

Index

Hellenica World - Scientific Library

Retrieved from "http://en.wikipedia.org/"
All text is available under the terms of the GNU Free Documentation License