ART

In mathematics, a representation is a very general relationship that expresses similarities (or equivalences) between mathematical objects or structures.[1] Roughly speaking, a collection Y of mathematical objects may be said to represent another collection X of objects, provided that the properties and relationships existing among the representing objects yi conform, in some consistent way, to those existing among the corresponding represented objects xi. More specifically, given a set Π of properties and relations, a Π-representation of some structure X is a structure Y that is the image of X under a homomorphism that preserves Π. The label representation is sometimes also applied to the homomorphism itself (such as group homomorphism in group theory).[2][3]

Representation theory

Perhaps the most well-developed example of this general notion is the subfield of abstract algebra called representation theory, which studies the representing of elements of algebraic structures by linear transformations of vector spaces.[3]
Other examples

Although the term representation theory is well established in the algebraic sense discussed above, there are many other uses of the term representation throughout mathematics.
Graph theory

An active area of graph theory is the exploration of isomorphisms between graphs and other structures. A key class of such problems stems from the fact that, like adjacency in undirected graphs, intersection of sets (or, more precisely, non-disjointness) is a symmetric relation. This gives rise to the study of intersection graphs for innumerable families of sets.[4] One foundational result here, due to Paul Erdős and his colleagues, is that every n-vertex graph may be represented in terms of intersection among subsets of a set of size no more than n2/4.[5]

Representing a graph by such algebraic structures as its adjacency matrix and Laplacian matrix gives rise to the field of spectral graph theory.[6]
Order theory

Dual to the observation above that every graph is an intersection graph is the fact that every partially ordered set (also known as poset) is isomorphic to a collection of sets ordered by the inclusion (or containment) relation ⊆. Some posets that arise as the inclusion orders for natural classes of objects include the Boolean lattices and the orders of dimension n.[7]

Many partial orders arise from (and thus can be represented by) collections of geometric objects. Among them are the n-ball orders. The 1-ball orders are the interval-containment orders, and the 2-ball orders are the so-called circle orders—the posets representable in terms of containment among disks in the plane. A particularly nice result in this field is the characterization of the planar graphs, as those graphs whose vertex-edge incidence relations are circle orders.[8]

There are also geometric representations that are not based on inclusion. Indeed, one of the best studied classes among these are the interval orders,[9] which represent the partial order in terms of what might be called disjoint precedence of intervals on the real line: each element x of the poset is represented by an interval [x1, x2], such that for any y and z in the poset, y is below z if and only if y2 < z1.
Logic

In logic, the representability of algebras as relational structures is often used to prove the equivalence of algebraic and relational semantics. Examples of this include Stone's representation of Boolean algebras as fields of sets,[10] Esakia's representation of Heyting algebras as Heyting algebras of sets,[11] and the study of representable relation algebras and representable cylindric algebras.[12]
Polysemy

Under certain circumstances, a single function f : X → Y is at once an isomorphism from several mathematical structures on X. Since each of those structures may be thought of, intuitively, as a meaning of the image Y (one of the things that Y is trying to tell us), this phenomenon is called polysemy—a term borrowed from linguistics. Some examples of polysemy include:

intersection polysemy—pairs of graphs G1 and G2 on a common vertex set V that can be simultaneously represented by a single collection of sets Sv, such that any distinct vertices u and w in V are adjacent in G1, if and only if their corresponding sets intersect ( Su ∩ Sw ≠ Ø ), and are adjacent in G2 if and only if the complements do ( SuC ∩ SwC ≠ Ø ).[13]

competition polysemy—motivated by the study of ecological food webs, in which pairs of species may have prey in common or have predators in common. A pair of graphs G1 and G2 on one vertex set is competition polysemic, if and only if there exists a single directed graph D on the same vertex set, such that any distinct vertices u and v are adjacent in G1, if and only if there is a vertex w such that both uw and vw are arcs in D, and are adjacent in G2, if and only if there is a vertex w such that both wu and wv are arcs in D.[14]

interval polysemy—pairs of posets P1 and P2 on a common ground set that can be simultaneously represented by a single collection of real intervals, that is an interval-order representation of P1 and an interval-containment representation of P2.[15]

See also

Group representation
Representation theorems
Model theory

References

"The Definitive Glossary of Higher Mathematical Jargon — Mathematical Representation". Math Vault. 2019-08-01. Retrieved 2019-12-07.
Weisstein, Eric W. "Group Representation". mathworld.wolfram.com. Retrieved 2019-12-07.
Teleman, Constantin. "Representation Theory" (PDF). math.berkeley.edu. Retrieved 2019-12-07.
McKee, Terry A.; McMorris, F. R. (1999), Topics in Intersection Graph Theory, SIAM Monographs on Discrete Mathematics and Applications, Philadelphia: Society for Industrial and Applied Mathematics, doi:10.1137/1.9780898719802, ISBN 978-0-89871-430-2, MR 1672910
Erdős, Paul; Goodman, A. W.; Pósa, Louis (1966), "The representation of a graph by set intersections", Canadian Journal of Mathematics, 18 (1): 106–112, CiteSeerX 10.1.1.210.6950, doi:10.4153/cjm-1966-014-3, MR 0186575
Biggs, Norman (1994), Algebraic Graph Theory, Cambridge Mathematical Library, Cambridge University Press, ISBN 978-0-521-45897-9, MR 1271140
Trotter, William T. (1992), Combinatorics and Partially Ordered Sets: Dimension Theory, Johns Hopkins Series in the Mathematical Sciences, Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press, ISBN 978-0-8018-4425-6, MR 1169299
Scheinerman, Edward (1991), "A note on planar graphs and circle orders", SIAM Journal on Discrete Mathematics, 4 (3): 448–451, doi:10.1137/0404040, MR 1105950
Fishburn, Peter C. (1985), Interval Orders and Interval Graphs: A Study of Partially Ordered Sets, Wiley-Interscience Series in Discrete Mathematics, John Wiley & Sons, ISBN 978-0-471-81284-5, MR 0776781
Marshall H. Stone (1936) "The Theory of Representations of Boolean Algebras," Transactions of the American Mathematical Society 40: 37-111.
Esakia, Leo (1974). "Topological Kripke models". Soviet Math. 15 (1): 147–151.
Hirsch, R.; Hodkinson, I. (2002). Relation Algebra by Games. Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics. 147. Elsevier Science.
Tanenbaum, Paul J. (1999), "Simultaneous intersection representation of pairs of graphs", Journal of Graph Theory, 32 (2): 171–190, doi:10.1002/(SICI)1097-0118(199910)32:2<171::AID-JGT7>3.0.CO;2-N, MR 1709659
Fischermann, Miranca; Knoben, Werner; Kremer, Dirk; Rautenbachh, Dieter (2004), "Competition polysemy", Discrete Mathematics, 282 (1–3): 251–255, doi:10.1016/j.disc.2003.11.014, MR 2059526
Tanenbaum, Paul J. (1996), "Simultaneous representation of interval and interval-containment orders", Order, 13 (4): 339–350, CiteSeerX 10.1.1.53.8988, doi:10.1007/BF00405593, MR 1452517

Undergraduate Texts in Mathematics

Graduate Texts in Mathematics

Graduate Studies in Mathematics

Mathematics Encyclopedia

World

Index

Hellenica World - Scientific Library

Retrieved from "http://en.wikipedia.org/"
All text is available under the terms of the GNU Free Documentation License